The “onion ring” model of pain


Clinicians constantly search for a better way to describe the tangled mess that constitutes ways to explore pain. Today I’m hoping to add another way, but hopefully one that might help disentangle certain aspects of pain for ease of learning. And as usual, it’s largely not my own model, but one first developed by Professor John Loeser, eminent neurologist and neurosurgeon and Director of the Multidisciplinary Pain Center from 1982-1997 at the University of Washington.

There are many different versions of the ‘Onion ring’ model – Gordon Waddell, orthopaedic surgeon and contemporary of Loeser also developed one, and more recently we’ve seen a version from Lorimer Moseley and colleagues in NOI publications. I’m going back to Loeser’s one because I think it’s useful – and in the case of conceptual models like this utility is the measure by which we decide to adopt a model or not. You be the judge. This is my public announcement that this is not intended to be a scientific model for generating and testing hypotheses: it’s meant to be an explanatory metaphor, if you like.

OK, so what is this model?

Like any onion, the model has inner to outer layers, but unlike an onion, these layers are permeable, and slightly fuzzy. They interact with one another, and the resultant whole is intended to reflect the experience of pain, along with the aspects that you and I might see – and includes various factors thought to influence the experience. It’s incomplete because much of what is known about pain is incomplete. It can’t explain everything, because no metaphor can – but it does provide some hooks for our minds to grab onto when we’re accessing new information and we want to establish relevance and recognition.

Loeser’s Onion Ring Model (1983)

The purple ring in the centre is all about neurobiology for me. Loeser’s original model labeled this “nociception”, but since 1983 we’ve learned a great deal more about the neurobiology of pain and we know that pain in the absence of nociception is probably a product of something gone awry in the way our nociceptive system is interpreting information. It could be neuropathic pain (where there is an identifiable lesion of the somatosensory system), or it might be nociplastic pain ( “pain that arises from altered nociception despite no clear evidence of actual or threatened tissue damage causing the activation of peripheral nociceptors or evidence for disease or lesion of the somatosensory system causing the pain.” – click). At this level of the model this is not pain. This inner ring refers only to biological processes prior to conscious awareness.

The next ring (dark blue) refers to the conscious experience we have of pain. This is the part we personally experience – it’s subjective, unpleasant, sensory and emotional, and we learn to associate this experience with potential or actual tissue damage, or we describe it in similar ways. In many respects this is the quale – the quality of what-it-is-like to experience pain – although others would argue it is an aporia (In philosophy, Aporia means literally ‘impasse, difficulty in passage, lack of resources, puzzlement’). However we like to define it, this part of Loeser’s model refers to the experience once our brain/mind has deemed it relevant to our predicament.

But, as the saying goes, wait! There’s more!

Because this dark blue ring is experiential, we can’t share it, or even know about another’s experience unless we do something about it, and before we do something about it, we appraise or judge it. With some provisos (told you this was a metaphor not a testable model!).

Drawing from cognitive models, Loeser then wraps another ring around the experience “pain” – this is what he described as suffering, but I prefer to describe as “judgement” or “appraisal”. Suffering is a judgement that this experience is threatening our essential self, our future (Cassel, 1999). So while there are certain behaviours that occur prior to awareness or judgement (see this) as soon as we are consciously aware of pain we’re judging that experience. And probably, because brains don’t just sit there waiting for information to come towards it, there is a good deal of permeability between the neurobiology ring, the pain-experience ring, and this ring. But for simplicity’s sake, let’s take it that when we experience “ouch” we typically check it out and interpret the meaning of that ouch in context of where we are, what we’re currently doing, who we’re with, and our past experiences. This interpretation or judgement phase can augment the meaning of pain to increase its threat value, or vice versa (OMG that was a snake bite! or Oh that was a bruise I didn’t need).

Wrapping around that “judgement” ring is a further ring – and this is possibly the one we most need to come to grips with. This ring is the behavioural response to our appraised experience. Pain behaviour or what we do when we recognise and judge our experience of pain is complex. It’s complex because all human behaviour is complex. It’s also complicated because we naively judge one another on the basis of what we see – and our own assumptions about what that behaviour might mean.

Behaviours include nocifensive responses, but don’t stop there. As we develop and mature from babyhood to adulthood, we embroider and alter our behavioural response to pain, just as we do with our appraisals. As babies we’re likely to scream our lungs out at the heel prick test at birth. I hope we don’t do that when we get a flu jab (and I truly hope you DO get a flu jab, and if you’re in Christchurch New Zealand that you get a measles immunisation pronto). We learn what to do from watching others (social learning), from others responses to us (operant conditioning), and from events that occur at the same time as our pain occurs (classical conditioning). Social learning is powerful – within different cultural groups, peer groups and family groups, we learn what is normal and OK to do when we’re sore. We also get rewarded (or not) for the way we behave. Little kids get told “stop that crying, it’s nothing” when they stub a toe, or they might get cuddled instead. Footballers get extra time if they roll around on the ground with an injury during a match; rugby players get adulation when they carry on playing despite a rib fracture or two. And for some people, associating a movement with pain can lead to longstanding limitations and avoiding that same movement in case it brings the pain on.

Pain behaviours include language and even that old “pain rating scale”. We use language and nonverbal behaviour to communicate. So when someone says “my pain is 12/10” what they’re really saying is “this is more than I can bear, help me”. We do not have a pure measure of how intense a pain is – and any measure of intensity is likely filtered through a process of judgement “what does this mean for me?” and communication “what will happen if I say X number?” So stop judging someone if they say their pain is 12/10 – it means they’re freaking out, and need comfort.

If you’re smart you’ll notice that I’ve sneakily been discussing the final onion ring, and to be fair, Loeser didn’t include this in his version – it’s one that Waddell, Main, and others have added and I think it’s integral to understanding what’s going on so I’ve added it too. The outer ring refers to the social context because this influences what people do (pain behaviours) as I’ve just outlined. It also includes social factors such as the workplace and compensation, legislation covering what is and isn’t covered in insurance plans, our community attitudes towards people who are experiencing pain, stigma and social isolation and sense of online community and such.

Loeser’s onion ring provides me with some nice ways to separate parts of my understanding of pain so I can explain how and why we need to examine them and influence them separately. Health professionals are always and inevitably influencing the judgement, behaviour, and social aspects of pain. Sometimes we get to influence the neurobiology and through interactions between all these layers, sometimes the experience of pain is reduced. Other times it is not. At the same time, if we can begin to shift the judgements and what we do about pain and yes, the social contexts in which experiencing weird unexplained pain is viewed as a moral failing or attempt to “get secondary gain”, maybe then we can help people live better lives despite their pain.

Cassell, E. J. (1999). Diagnosing Suffering: A Perspective. Annals of Internal Medicine, 131(7), 531-534. doi:10.7326/0003-4819-131-7-199910050-00009

Loeser JD, Ford WE. Chronic Pain. In: Carr JE, Dengerink HA, (eds). Behavioral Science in the Practice of Medicine. New York: Elsevier Biomedical:1983:331-345

Advertisements

5 comments

  1. Bronnie, I heartily concur with your concluding remarks:

    “At the same time, if we can begin to shift the judgements and what we do about pain and yes, the social contexts in which experiencing weird unexplained pain is viewed as a moral failing or attempt to “get secondary gain”, maybe then we can help people live better lives despite their pain”.

    However, I am disappointed that you made no mention of our critique of the “onion ring” models that is contained in our 2008 paper.*

    In this paper, we did point out some of the problems, not the least of which is the role of the observer. How can health care professionals/observers be expected to determine the relative importance of the content of each of the layers they are invited to dissect?

    Our other serious criticism is that the models leave out the person experiencing pain. This was a central component of Engel’s biopsychosocial model that was entirely overlooked by John Loeser and Gordon Waddell when they adapted it for pain medicine. The application of their models seems to have precluded inter-subjectivity from entering the clinical engagement.

    *Quintner JL, Buchanan D, Cohen ML. Katz J, Williamson O. Pain medicine and its models: helping or hindering? Pain Medicine 2008; 9: 824-834.

    1. Thanks for taking the time to comment John. I’m a little puzzled at your comments about this model failing to take into account the perspective of the person, for how would we unravel the various layers (particularly of the experience, the appraisals and contextual influences) without the involvement of the person? I think this model invites people including those with pain and those who would hope to help them, to understand that it is impossible to (a) directly understand another person’s pain (b) judge the thoughts and resultant behaviours negatively, and (c) construe of pain as anything other than a complex emergent experience. I think this particular model is entirely about the person from his or her perspective (or, more correctly, in collaboration with a clinician who may posit the relevant biological elements, and invite discussion of the appraisals and contextual factors influencing behaviour). It is not my intention to suggest that the observer has a position to judge the relevance of factors contributing to our experience of pain. Indeed, I think this is a collaborative process because as individuals we’re prone to cognitive and perceptual bias, while both clinicians and people experiencing pain bring their wealth of knowledge to the situation. I’m sure you’d agree with this.
      I think you may have misconstrued Loeser’s model – it is about and with the person, rather than as an “outsider looking in”. It allows clinicians to be aware that there is much they are completely oblivious to (the actual “pain” experience being the key aspect) whereas prior to introducing this model, clinicians have assumed (and still do) that what they observe either actually represents pain OR that it is irrelevant without neurobiology or tissue damage.
      We may beg to differ, but I don’t think the model is at fault as much as how it may be employed – and that can be said about much in healthcare.

      1. Bronnie, when reflecting on the “onion” analogy for pain, I decided to adapt this aphorism about “Life” by the American writer, James Huneker [1857-1921}: “Pain is like an onion: you peel off layer after layer and then you find that there is nothing in it.”

        Yes, we do beg to differ on this issue.

      2. A lot like baking a cake: we can analyse the components, and woe betide if they’re out of proportion to one another, or if the eggs are rotten or the flour isn’t the right kind, because the outcome isn’t pretty. But in the end, without all the components, the cake is not a thing. Similarly for an onion – if we analyse all the bits and pieces, and try to understand them separately, we lose a great deal in the process – yes, it’s still oniony, but it’s not the same as the whole thing. And that’s the way I think we can view people’s experience of pain. We can fail to analyse the components and not be able to understand much of what makes pain pain, or we can analyse each layer and fail to pull them all together. Or we can both analyse in collaboration with the person with both of our combined expertise contributing, and become more able to help one another be aware of various aspects that add to the experience. While pain is a complex emergent experience, there’s no doubt that various parts of that experience ARE open to analysis by BOTH parties – and sometimes we need each other to be able to make sense of it all. The bits that are missing are the contributions from wise elders who can comment on socio-cultural aspects, and the meaning and relevance of the experience. This is where history and external others can be very helpful.

      3. Bronnie, with respect, when I bake a cake I like to know all the ingredients beforehand. But following on from your “onion ring” analogy, would you not agree that we might fail in our attempts to reverse engineer a chocolate sponge cake (for example)?

        So it is for pain, an experience that we cannot reverse engineer and thereby dissect out the various components with any degree of accuracy.

        Whenever I peel onions, there is always the likelihood that I will shed tears. I would concede this analogy is apt whenever I try to understand the meaning and relevance of another person’s experience.

        However, I think we are close to agreement. Can I suggest that your analysis fits very neatly into the concept of a truly inter-subjective (“third space”) approach? If this is what John Loeser intended, I heartily approve.

Leave a Reply

Fill in your details below or click an icon to log in:

WordPress.com Logo

You are commenting using your WordPress.com account. Log Out /  Change )

Google photo

You are commenting using your Google account. Log Out /  Change )

Twitter picture

You are commenting using your Twitter account. Log Out /  Change )

Facebook photo

You are commenting using your Facebook account. Log Out /  Change )

Connecting to %s

This site uses Akismet to reduce spam. Learn how your comment data is processed.